Monday, November 3, 2014

The Equality Emotion


Contemporary political discourse is abundantly supplied with uses and abuses of the term ‘equality.’ Individuals generously spread the word around like a fine garnish on a main course – or bitter herb, depending on your seat at the table. If marriage rights are on the table for discussion, prepare for a lavish helping of equality rhetoric. If voting rights are on the debate menu, again prepare for more equality talk. At times, the word is garnished so deep, that one never gets fed the meat and potatoes of the argument.

            For all our contemporary reliance on this single term, one would expect that we know what it means. But do we? Is it possible that the term is almost meaningless filler—like garnish—spread around for presentation? Peter Western, professor of law, persuasively argues that the term ‘equality’ is garnish—or, again, bitter herb, perspective. I diverge from Western, but only slightly. But before I get to my views, I think it important to show how nearly empty ‘equality’ is of conceptual content.

            Western notes that ‘equality’ is oft defined as “[people] that are alike should be treated alike, while [people] that are unlike should be treated unalike in proportion to their unalikeness.”[1] The primary consideration, then, becomes determining precisely what it means for two person two be alike. It might mean “alike in every respect.”[2] But “the only things that are completely alike in every respect are immaterial symbols and forms[.]” No two persons, not even identical twins, are alike in every respect.

            Alternatively, “people who are alike” may mean “alike in some respects.” Id. This proposal, Western notes, won’t work either. Under the previous definition, every person is excluded, since no two people are exactly alike. Id. Under this definition, “every person and thing” are included “because all people and things are alike in some respect[.]” Id. For example, my desk and I both take up space. A woman and a fox both have eyes. Pick any two objects or people and you can find something they have in common. So, under this definition “one is left with the morally absurd proposition that “all people and things should be treated alike.”[3]

            Finally, Western proposes that “people who are alike” could refer to “people who are morally alike in a certain respect.”[4] The problem, however, is that “categories of morally alike objects do not exist in nature; moral alikeness is established only when people define categories.”[5] Thus, “[t]o say that people are morally alike is therefore to articulate a moral standard of treatment . . . by reference to which they are, and thus are to be treated, alike.”[6] This moral standard fixes both how people are alike and how they are to be treated owing to the fact that they are alike. In a nutshell this definition requires “that people for whom a certain treatment is prescribed by a standard should be given the treatment prescribed by the standard.”[7] Thus, ‘equality’ is not an empty concept, for Western, it is a mere tautology.[8] In other words, the concept is not empty, but it is wholly uninformative. We should treat people who are morally alike—as determined by a moral standard—the treatment that the moral standard prescribes for people morally alike.
            Several scholars, less than enchanted about Western’s argument, have provided intriguing responses.[9] One scholar argues that Western’s analysis of ‘equality’ provides too narrow a construction of the term. A broader understanding of ‘equality,’ or so the argument goes, “. . . evokes a particular range of moral considerations and a particular set of complex arguments, and it does that, not by virtue of its meaning, but because every political theorist is familiar with a tradition of argumentation in and around certain texts and doctrines and knows that colleagues can be alerted to the possible relevance of that tradition by using that simple word.”[10]

            While this argument clarifies the meaning of ‘equality’ in the ivory tower of the university, it provides no clarification of what the term means when uttered in the streets. When an average citizen utters ‘equality,’ are they ‘evoking a particular range of moral considerations and a particular set of complex arguments . . . [since] they are familiar with a tradition of argumentation in and around certain texts and doctrines and knows that [others] can be alerted to the possible relevance of that tradition by using that simple word”? I highly doubt it. The average citizen is familiar with certain historical conflicts for equality: slavery, civil rights, women’s rights, etc. Further, the average citizen’s awareness of these events is cursory and simplistic. There is no detailed information of texts and arguments from the era. Instead, our average citizen is familiar with who the oppressors were, what they were denying the oppressed, and with the outcome: the oppressors are now on the “wrong side of history.”
            Such broad generalizations and oversimplifications of history—while partially correct in spirit—lead to moral outrage and emotive fanaticism. When our average citizen, unread in law and history, utters ‘equality,’ he invokes an image or mood from history. This simplistic image or mood galvanizes emotional outbursts spurred on by the citizen’s historical sense of rightness. He begins seeing himself as the oppressed or liberator of the oppressed. He sees those who hold different views as the oppressors on the wrong side of history. Before long, our citizen is taken away into an emotional fugue state, saying things no reasonable person would say to another.

The problem with ‘equality’ is that users and abusers of the term are free to fill whatever imagery or content they want into it. Even worse, key political players are able to manipulate individuals by filling imagery and emotive content into the term. As for me, then, I don’t see ‘equality’ as a nice garnish or a bitter herb, but as a hallucinogen. Those who eat too much of it are intoxicated with an inappropriate sense of self-righteousness. Their public manners fade and they have no reservations, shouting abuses at the opposing side. The more they shout, the more they become intoxicated. And as they become more intoxicated, their sense of self-righteousness is heightened. With such individuals, it is strangely that which goes into the body and that which comes out that defiles them; it is, after all, the same thing in this case. My recommendation is to use the term ‘equality’ thoughtfully. Familiarize yourself with the origins of the word, its development through concrete historical events, and the complex legal, moral, and philosophical arguments surrounding its use.[11] And, if you can't use the term without emotional outbursts and feelings of resentment or hatred, better for all involved if you eliminate it altogether from your debate diet.




[1] Peter Westen, The Empty Idea of Equality, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 537, 543 (1982). 
[2] Id., at 544.
[3] Id.
[4] Id.
[5] Id. at 545.
[6] Id.
[7] Id. at 547.
[8] Id. at 547 – 48.
[9] See e.g., Kent Greenawalt, How Empty Is the Idea of Equality?, 83 Colum. L. Rev. 1167 (1983); and Anthony D’Amato, Is Equality a Totally Empty Idea?, 81 Mich. L. Rev. 600 (1983).
[10] Jeremy Waldron, 89 Mich. L. Rev. 1350, 1352 (1991).
[11] Again, the term may possess little content. Yet, following Jeremy Waldron's lead, historical awareness of the term at least provides context for its appropriate use, minimizing inappropriate abuses.

No comments:

Post a Comment