A basic, yet crucial, distinction in philosophical
explanations concerns the difference between abstract and concrete entities. An
abstract entity is not located in space-time and does not stand in causal
relations to other entities (e.g. numbers and propositions). A concrete entity is located in space-time and does
stand in causal relations to other entities (e.g. rocks, rivers, mountains and stars). Philosophers frequently reference
both types of entities when providing explanations for various phenomena.
Typically, abstract entities are taken up to explain why concrete entities are
the way they are.
For example, Plato invoked forms, abstract entities which
explain why things are the way they are, how they are meaningful to us, and how
we can recognize disparate instances of them.
A chair, as the theory goes, is meaningful by its participating—this is
not a causal relationship as forms qua abstract entities don’t enter into
causal relations—in the form of chairness. That form is what we intuit when we
look at a chair. It provides an explanation of how the particular chair is meaningful
and how we can recognize objects that are completely dissimilar as chairs.
Further, in an elaborate myth of how the world was created, Plato posited a
demiurge that modeled concrete, physical objects after the intelligible forms.
Christians, who appropriated Neo-Platonism would later claim that the forms
reside in the mind of God and that God used these intelligible principles to
model the world. This schema leads to the beautiful conclusion that whenever
you have an experience of meaning—which is during every conscious moment—it is
because your consciousness is subtly enveloped in the mind of God in such a way
that entities are illuminated for you. Each conscious experience is made
possible by being wrapped up into the mind of God—the ground of all Being.
Currently, however, there is a trend amongst the
scientifically minded and among philosophers that wish to model philosophical
explanations after scientific ones, to completely discredit the existence of
abstract entities. Foremost amongst philosophers in this regard is David
Armstrong. In arguing for the nonexistence of abstract entities, Armstrong
invoked Ockham’s Razor—a primary tool in distinguishing between parsimonious
scientific theories and those which are over-encumbered with unneeded explanans (i.e. things which explain).
In short, Ockham’s Razor is the requirement that “entities are not to be
multiplied without necessity.” Russell, Our
Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy
(London: Routledge, 1914), 107. Drawing upon this time honored principle,
Armstrong levels the following argument against abstract entities:
(1) Abstract entities, unlike concrete entities, do not
exist in space-time.
(2) If objects do not exist in space-time they are not
causally related to other objects.
(C1) So, even if abstract entities exist, they would make no
causal difference to concrete entities. (By modus
ponens with the implicit premise that concrete entities are in space and
time and thus are causally related).
(C2) Abstract entities, even if they exist, provide no
causal explanation for concrete entities.
(C3) Thus, there is no reason to suppose the existence of
abstract entities.
See Armstrong,
D.M., Nominalism and Realism: Universals
and Scientific Realism, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1978), 130.
This argument, demonstrating no “reason” for the existence
of abstract entities, is intended to take us to the conclusion that without a
reason for the existence of some entity, we ought not believe that it exists—i.e.
we have the epistemic duty to withhold belief. Armstrong’s argument may appear
detached from any practical concerns of daily life. However, if his argument
succeeds, much of traditional philosophy and western religious theology will
have been undermined. Further, the reason that I selected Armstrong’s argument
is because it is representative of many attitudes of the scientifically
inducted. I have oft heard individuals claim that since science does not need
to invoke abstract entities, including God, to explain concrete/physical
phenomena, then there is no reason to believe in those things. Armstrong
captures with precision these sentiments.
However, Armstrong’s conclusion rests on a questionable
inference. C2 speaks of “causal explanations.” Thereafter, Armstrong’s argument
abruptly turns to “reasons;” “there is no reason to suppose the existence of
abstract entities.” In other words, Armstrong seems to be claiming that causal
explanations are the only types of explanations that provide reasons for
believing one way or the other. This is unsurprising since scientific
theorizing rests, more often than not, upon plotting out the causal connections
underlying phenomena as a way of reductively explaining them. Yet, causal
explanations are not the only type of explanation which provides “reasons” for
believing. The principles in geometry and statistics are used heavily in various
scientific fields as bases of scientific explanations. These appropriated
principles are often, importantly, not causal. In fact, much of the scientific
reasoning underlying all of scientific theorizing (e.g. verificationist and falsificationist
schemes) is not causal in nature. Causality is not the only type of explanation
which provides reasons for believing things. And even though the scientist qua
scientist is urged, more often than not, to ignore non-causal explanations for
purposes of the scientific process, we ought not, as the scientifically minded Positivists
frequently quipped, mistake our scientific models for reality.
Reality is broader and various forms of explanations, not
just causal explanations provided by concrete entities, provide a roadmap in
understanding it. The wisest of philosophers and theologians have for centuries
recognized this principle. Their struggle to find a rational explanation for
reality as such has repeatedly led these sages to posit abstract entities. Does
this mean that abstract entities (e.g. numbers, forms and certain notions God)
must exist? Well, if the ancients are correct, abstract entities oft provide
the very best explanation, and at time the only explanation, for various
concrete phenomena. In these extreme instances it appears that they must exist.
This philosophical argument has not, importantly, proven that abstract entities
do conclusively exist. What is has attempted to demonstrate is that the
prevailing attitude which snubs abstract entities as sound principles for explanation,
since science doesn’t need to rely on them, rests upon faulty reasoning.
Barring stronger arguments from scientific materialists, we should not be
ashamed to invoke non-causal, philosophical/theological explanations for the
world around us—assuming of course that the explanations we invoke are grounded
upon sound reasons.
I feel a little arrogant saying this, but Armstrong's argument is just, well, bad. Does he really make no effort to explain that all explanations must be causal? Does he even realize he holds that supposition?
ReplyDeletePerhaps what he really means to argue is that abstract entities are entirely separate from concrete ones, which means that abstract entities are completely irrelevant and unrelated to concrete ones. This would, of course, make is impossible to explain concrete entities in virtue of abstract ones. This would strike me as a valid argument. Its cogency, on the other hand, could be debated, and given your background with Plato, I'm sure you could argue for the existence and relevance of abstract entities quite powerfully.
You've pointed out the conundrum of positivism and materialism: science boils down to science, which boils down to science, which boils down to science, etc.. In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein compares concepts to pictures of reality. The form of the picture is equivalent to logic. We can't conceptualize about logic because logic is itself the form of conceptualization. This means we can only speak about concepts and the objects which they represent, which means science is the sole source of knowledge about that which we can speak (he changes this stance I believe in Philosophical Investigations). Anyway, for Wittgenstein, while he would have said in the Tractatus that our knowledge comes from the natural sciences, it comes only through the form of knowledge: logic. Logic is the means through which we even attain conceptual knowledge. When the form of concept is lost -- perhaps the Platonists call this form the realm of abstract entities -- it seems to me that we rid ourselves of the very means through which we even have knowledge; we essentially take away an artist's canvass but leave him with the paint and the paintbrushes.
So what prompted you to write a blog about this topic?