Friday, July 5, 2013

Is Ethical Relativism Possible?


I fear our era has succumbed to ethical relativism—the view that there are no objective standards of right and wrong holding for all historical epochs, cultures, or individuals. “Different strokes for different folks,” is the anthem of our generation. “It is right for him,” or “that is her morality,” are regular facets of the relativists' discourse.       

Ironically, in my experience, those most committed to ethical relativism are unable to maintain their “enlightened,” views in practice. Emotion filled injunctions against war, torture, racisim and cultural imperialism are equally common facets of their discourse. If you doubt this, I encourage you to tell an ethical relativist that it is your morality to force your morality onto others. See how long they continue to sing their “different strokes for different folks,” anthem. While such observations indicate that ethical relativism is untenable in practice, I maintain that it is self-contradictory, on a conceptual level.

To see this, note that adherents—at least when they are not in an emotional fugue state— marshal arguments against objective moral standards. A common argument points to wide differences in cultural norms and mores, inferring that this evidence conclusively demonstrates the nonexistence of objective moral standards.[1] Whatever the virtues of such an argument are, it is important to note that all such arguments—and all arguments in general—rest on an implicit premise: if the argument is sound or cogent, we ought to accept it. In other words, it would be wrong to withhold our accent. Alternatively, it would be right or good to accent. Apparently, such arguments are supposed to be valid for all historical epochs, cultures or individuals. If I argue that cultural norms have varied throughout history and moral norms are therefore relative to historical epoch and culture, I am claiming that such observations would hold regardless of their time or location of utterance, and that therefore we ought to accept the inferred conclusion.

The normative terms, right, good, and ought, are presupposed with every argument. In fact, ethical relativists cannot offer any argument for their position without presupposing the imperative force their arguments should have for any person, at any place, during any time. The fact that such terms cannot be denied without contradiction indicates that their content—viz., goodness, rightness, etc.—is a basic feature of human cognition. We cannot engage in discourse, nor have knowledge of the world, free of such features.

In fact, an ethical relativist cannot escape the conclusion I have offered here without presupposing the content of those normative terms. For assume that a proponent were to argue against what I have said here. For example, he argues that my observations, as to the normative structure of argumentation, are flawed; or that relativists do not assume that their arguments hold across all times, places, or individuals. In rolling out his argument and positing his conclusion, the relativist would claim that “for these reasons we ought to reject what has been said here.” His argument would apparently apply to any similar observations, as to the normative structure of argumentation, regardless of time, location or person making such observations; or that relativists, regardless of time, location or proponent, do not make such assumptions. In other words, the ethical relativist, whatever the argument, cannot argue against what I have said here without presupposing the normative term, ought, good, or right.

Importantly, the foregoing normative terms are the basic terms employed in all ethical discourse. If they are a basic feature of human cognition, as I have argued here, their use can extend beyond argumentation, touching various fixtures of reality. Ethical relativism cannot argue against the objective existence of such terms without presupposing them. Perhaps I am wrong. If so, I invite the ethical relativist to present an argument that we ought to accept, contrary to what I have said here. In so doing, perhaps the proponent can rescue relativism from its self-contradiction and reestablishing it as a theory that ought to apply to all individuals, across all cultural and historical epochs. Needless to say, I won’t hold my breath. 



[1] In my experience, if proponents offer arguments at all, they are not much more sophisticated than this. Yet, it must be noted that there are numerous sophisticated arguments for ethical relativism. Presenting such arguments is unnecessary for my purposes. My observations will point out general features common to all argumentation, however sophisticated. 

No comments:

Post a Comment