Since its initial publication in a
1982 article entitled “Epiphenomenal Qualia,” Frank Jackson’s thought
experiment involving Mary, a brilliant scientist, has been met with a
voluminous amount of literature intending to refute the experiment. This
response was to be expected. After all, if the thought experiment stands, then
physicalism becomes an untenable ontological position and the belief that
mental states can be reduced to gray matter will be a shipwrecked enterprise.
In this paper, I will defend Jackson’s thought experiment from one of its more
radical critiques as given by Daniel Dennett. I will show that Dennett’s
critique is actually a red herring and as such does no damage to Jackson’s
argument.
In Jackson’s experiment, Mary a
brilliant young scientist, is “forced to investigate the world from a black and
white room via a black and white television monitor” (Jackson 1982, p. 130). In
this condition Mary is completely deprived of any color experiences. However,
through this investigation Mary is able to acquire all physical facts pertaining to color vision. She understands, in
the most exacting of detail, everything that goes into the formation of a color
experience. She “discovers, for example, just which wave-length combinations
from the sky stimulate the retina, and exactly how this produces, via the
central nervous system the contraction of the vocal chords and expulsion of air
from the lungs that results in the uttering of the sentence “the sky is blue””
(Jackson 1982, p. 130).
When Mary is eventually released
from this controlled environment to experience
color for the first time, it is clear that she will learn something new
about color—specifically, what various colors look like. Even though Mary knows
everything there is to know about the physiology and physics of blue, as
experienced when looking at the sky, it is clear that upon first seeing a blue
sky she is learning something new; viz. the
phenomenal feel of “sky blue.” Yet, if Mary learns something new, “then it is
inescapable that her previous knowledge was incomplete. But she had all the
physical information. Ergo there is
more to have than that, and Physicalism is false” (Jackson 1982, p. 130).
It is hard to overestimate the
ramifications of this thought experiment. If Jackson is right, then all facts
in the universe are not physical facts. There are also phenomenal facts which
are of a different kind. If this is the case, then physicalist ontology is a
dead enterprise. For the sake of precision and forthcoming analysis, I will set
forth Jackson’s argument into premise and conclusion format:
1.
Before
her release from her black and white environment, Mary had all physical
information about various color experiences.
2.
Upon
her release Mary, for the first time, experiences what it is like to see
various colors. Through these experiences Mary acquired new information—i.e.
information pertaining to the phenomenal property of what it is like to see a
particular color.
3.
If
Mary were to acquire new information outside of the room, then that information
would be nonphysical (by definition from 1)
C1.
Upon her release, Mary obtained information which was nonphysical (modus ponens by 2, 3)
4.
If
Mary acquired information which was nonphysical, then it pertained to a
nonphysical property of the color experience.
C2.
The information Mary received via experiencing color demonstrates that there is
a nonphysical property pertaining to the experience of color (modus ponens by C1, 4).
5.
If
color experiences have a component which is nonphysical it follows, by
definition, that physicalism is false (by definition from physicalism).
C3.
Physicalism is false (modus ponens by
C2, 5).
Before
moving onto Dennett’s attempted refutation of this argument, it is important to
point out the full implications of Jackson’s thought experiment. Specifically,
even though this thought experiment analyzes a singular sense modality, it
could, in principle, be extended to all
sense modalities. It is easy to imagine a similar thought experiment for
tactile, auditory and olfactory experiences—in short for all sense experiences.
Consequently, the Mary experiment purports to show that the most basic building
blocks of conscious experience, qualia,
cannot be accounted for via physicalism.
DANIEL DENNETT AND MARY
The philosopher Daniel Dennett
objects to Jackson’s thought experiment outright. Specifically Dennett claims
that Jackson has given us “a bad thought experiment, an intuition pump that
actually encourages us to misunderstand its premises” (Dennett 1991, p. 399).
In other words, Jackson’s thought experiment plays on un-tuned intuition as to
what physical information can reveal. From here, he makes an easy transition to
its conclusion “physicalism is false.” According to Dennett,
“The image is wrong; if that is the way you
imagine the case, you are simply not following directions! The reason no one
follows directions is because what they ask you to imagine is so preposterously
immense, you can’t even try. The crucial premise is that “She has all the
physical information.” That is not readily imaginable, so no one bothers. They
just imagine that she knows lots and lots—perhaps they imagine that she knows
everything that anyone knows today about the neurophysiology of color vision.
But that’s just a drop in the bucket, and it’s not surprising that Mary would
learn something if that were all she knew.”
So Dennett will run the thought experiment over again,
taking very seriously the claim that Mary possess all physical information pertaining to color vision. This emphasis
will be a key point in Dennett’s denial of the second premise in Jackson’s
argument above. If Dennett can establish his case then the rest of Jackson’s
argument from premise two onwards will be false. By encouraging us to take
seriously the claim that Mary has all the
physical information Dennett hopes to tune our intuitions into greater clarity,
thus allowing us to see that Jackson’s thought experiment does not prove
anything at all. In order to achieve the greatest clarity possible, I will
simply cite the thought experiment Dennett gives at length:
And so, one day, Mary’s
captors decided it was time for her to see colors. As a trick, they prepared a
bright blue banana to present as her first color experience ever. Mary took one
look at it and said “Hey! You tried to trick me! Bananas are yellow, but this
one is blue!” her captors were dumfounded. How did she do it? “Simple,” she
replied. “You have to remember that I know everything—absolutely
everything—that could ever be known about the physical casues and effects of
color vision. So of course before you brought the banana in, I had already
written down, in exquisite detail, exactly what physical impression a yellow
object or a blue object (or a green object, etc.) would make on my nervous
system. So I already knew exactly what thought I would have (because, after
all, the “mere disposition” to think about this or that is not one your famous
qualia, is it?). I was not in the slightest surprised by my experience of blue
(what surprised me was that you would try such a second-rate trick on me). I realize
it is hard for you to imagine that I
could know so much about my reactive dispositions that the way blue affected me
came as no surprise. Of course it’s hard for you to imagine. It’s hard for
anyone to imagine the consequences of someone knowing absolutely everything
physical about anything!” (Dennett 1991, p. 399-400)
How
Dennett envisions Mary being able to accomplish such a feat is not wholly
clear. To be sure, she has all the physical facts, providing information far
above and beyond anything our intuitions can currently imagine. However, even
though Dennett assures this, it appears he believes Mary has to perform some
type of inference in order to get at the phenomenal data of a color experience.
Specifically,
Dennett claims that Mary has a great deal of knowledge at her disposal already.
She already knows varying shades of gray; the difference between “such surface
properties as glossiness versus matte, and she knows the difference between
luminance boundaries and color boundaries” (Dennett 1991, p. 400). All of this information
is combined with detailed knowledge of how her Nervous system will react to any
given wavelength of light. In Dennett’s words,
the only task that
remains is for her to figure out a way of identifying those neurophysiological
effects “from the inside.” You may find you can readily imagine her making a little progress on this—for instance,
figuring out tricky ways in which she
would be able to tell that some color, whatever it is, is not yellow, or not
red. How? By noting some salient and specific reaction her brain would have
only for yellow or only for red. But if you allow her even a little entry into
her color space in this way, you should conclude that she can leverage her way
to complete advance knowledge, because she doesn’t just know the salient reactions, she knows them all
(Dennett 1991, p. 400-01)
So,
it seems clear that Dennett’s explanation to render plausible exactly how Mary
is gaining her knowledge of color experience is via inference from information
she already has.
In
the end, Dennett’s position seems strong and clear. We cannot possibly know
what possessing all physical information pertaining to a given domain would be
like. In order to reach a sweeping ontological conclusion (i.e. physicalism is
false) based on our current intuitions as to what physical information can be
said to provide, is premature at best.
WHY DENNETT IS WRONG
I think it can be established that
Jackson has not given us a mere intuition pump and that Dennett has actually
provided us with an elaborate red herring. In order to demonstrate that point I
will run the thought experiment again, in a modified form, with the hopes that
Dennett’s faulty reasoning can be exposed. However, before I undertake that
endeavor, I would like to acknowledge two points by way of critique. These need
to be set forth to adequately prepare the ground for my thought experiment.
First, I would like to hone in on
Dennett’s Mary. In order to render plausible the idea that Mary has not learned
anything new at all, Dennett focuses on her ability to distinguish colors. She
knew she was being tricked when she was handed a bright blue banana. She was
able to accomplish this feat through a detailed knowledge of her nervous system
and how it would react with varying wavelengths of light. This characterization
of the situation does not demonstrate that Mary hasn’t learned anything new
though. All Dennett has demonstrated is that Mary has “know how” when it comes
to distinguishing colors. To be sure, “know how” is likely a necessary
condition in saying whether someone has knowledge of different colors. If May
were unable to distinguish a blue banana from a yellow one, we would not say
that she had the relevant knowledge of colors.
Even though “know how” may be
necessary condition in saying whether someone has knowledge of color, it is not
sufficient. We can imagine Mary distinguishing colors merely by the behavior of
her central nervous system. She may have no clue that blue has that type of look and feel and yet “know how” to distinguish it from yellow merely by
noting that the patterns of firing produced in her central nervous system do
not conform to the physical information she already possesses in regards to
color interaction with her nervous system. So, “know how” is not sufficient to
prove Dennett’s case. In effect, it appears that Dennett has tried to conflate
notions of “know how” with “know that” in order to make his thought experiment
more plausible. However, in so doing he has presented us with a red herring
that detracts us from the original question: Does Mary learn anything new? We
are looking for indications that Mary has gained “know that,” not merely “know
how.” The possession of “know how” with all physical information is not all
that implausible, even for Jackson’s Mary.
Second, Dennett is encouraging us to
dispel our intuitions in regards to what type of knowledge physical information
could provide. Essentially, he is claiming that with a complete inventory of
all the physical information—a situation we can’t currently imagine—qualia will come along for free. In
other words, complete physical information will allow us to gain knowledge of qualia experiences free of those
experiences themselves. Dennett recognizes that physical facts, as currently
envisioned, cannot perform the feat he is requiring of them. So, he asks us to
write a blank check against our well-trained intuitions in anticipation of the
problem being resolves with an exhaustive inventory of the physical facts. The
problem with this whole set up, is that Dennett emphasizes the problem as being
one of quantity—we do not have all the
physical information—not one of quality. Knowledge gained via inference from physical facts to particular quale is qualitatively different than
knowledge gained by a direct experience of those quale themselves.
In essence, all physical information
gives Mary a foothold from where she can infer her way to a full knowledge of qualia. As Dennett puts it, “if you
allow her even a little entry into her color space in this way . . . she can
leverage her way to complete advance knowledge, because she doesn’t just know
the salient reactions, she knows them
all” (Dennett 1991, p. 400-01). The difficulties associated with a serious
defense of this position are paramount. Perhaps foremost is the difficulty of
establishing that knowledge of qualia
gained by inference has the same modal quality as knowledge gained by direct
experiences. No matter how sound an inference may be, the possibility of error
is always looming and with it the possibility that our judgment concerning some
entity or entities, in this case qualia,
may in fact be incorrect. The same cannot be said of a direct experience of a quale, say the color red. It is not in
doubt whether or not I am seeing that color, there, right in front of me.
Furthermore, it is not in doubt whether or not that color there has the
properties I see it to have. My knowledge is direct and therefore indubitable.
To be sure, I can doubt whether or not I am applying the term “red” in the same
manner as the community at large. However, that is tangential to the issue. Our
knowledge, from a direct experience of a quale
is of a different modal quality than knowledge gained by an inference.
Consequently, it seems clear that all the
physical facts does not get us the same type
of knowledge that direct experience does. Hence, Mary would learn something
new upon leaving her black-and-white room for the first time.
So,
with Dennett conflating notions of “know how” and “know that” and with it
apparent that we cannot even conceive of what type of physical information
would provide us undubitable knowledge of qualia
experiences free from those experiences themselves, it becomes clear that
Dennett has not made his case that Jackson has given us a mere intuition pump.
Jackson is not solely playing on our intuitions. He is leveraging our best
understanding of what physical information can be taken to demonstrate. Free of
some radical new understanding of how physical information, even all physical
information in a given domain, could be used to achieved knowledge with the
characteristics ascribed to qualia,
we are not compelled to accept Dennett’s conclusions. Dennett asks us to write
a blank check, claiming that some day all physical information will be able to
account for all the facts within the universe. With no indication of whether or
not Dennett’s gamble is right, it would be unwise to accept his invitation.
MARY THOUGHT EXPERIMENT CONTRA DENNETT
With the key information in place,
and with a preliminary critique, I can now run Jackson’s thought experiment
over again from a different angle. This time, I will employ two Marys, Mary 1
and Mary 2. Running the thought experiment with separate Marys in tandem will
allow me to use one Mary as a control. This control will allow us to see the
difference between “know how” and “know that” knowledge, as well as
demonstrating that knowledge via nervous system inference is not of the same
character as knowledge via direct experience.
Mary1 and Mary2 have
been forced to investigate the world through a black-and-white room. In this
condition they are able to obtain all the
physical facts pertaining to color vision. To have all the physical facts pertaining to color vision is to fully and
completely exhaust all possible physical information on the subject. To be
sure, we cannot imagine what it would be like to have all physical information
on this given subject, since our current understanding of the human nervous
system is in its infancy. The information it provides may be far grandeur than
we could imagine, exceeding even our greatest expectations.
Those who have placed Mary1 and
Mary2 in there black-and-white cells have every intention of
releasing them into the world. However, before they do, they decide, at random,
to use Mary1 as a control. In essence, the put Mary1
under the knife, ablating critical connections to the cortical regions
responsible for color processing. Since Mary1 has all physical facts pertaining to color
vision, she knows exactly how this procedure has effected her nervous system
and will be able to compensate for it when seeing color. As Mary1 and
Mary2 first color experience, her captures have prepared a bright
blue banana. Upon being presented with this banana, Mary1 appears
shocked. She cannot believe that her captors have played such a trick on her.
She tells them that the banana is a lighter shade of blue and not yellow like
bananas are supposed to be. When they asked her how she accomplished such a
feat, she responded that she knew in acute detail how the wavelengths would
react with her retina and the associated portions of her cerebral cortex,
including how the ablations would effect the flow and process of visual
information. She knew how to distinguish sky blue from yellow due to this
information.
In a parallel room, Mary2
is also handed a sky blue banana. Upon being handed the banana Mary2 is
also stunned that her captors would play such a trick on her. When asked how
she knew that the banana was not yellow, she gave much the same response as
Mary1. However, unlike Mary1, Mary2 is
actually having the experience of sky
blue. This experience, or “the what it feels like” of sky blue is
information which Mary1 does not have at her disposal. Consequently,
it seems clear that mary2 has gained nonphysical information not
available to Mary1. Therefore, not all facts in the universe are
physical facts and physicalism is false.
Dennett may be inclined to respond
with the same line of attack with which he started, i.e. I am not taking
seriously the claim that Mary1 has all physical information about color vision. This includes her
exhaustive information of Mary2 and her healthy, functioning nervous
system. Consequently, she would know, in rich detail, how such an experience
must be for Mary2. So, Mary2, has not gained information
unavailable to Mary1. In response, it may become immediately clear
how inadequate this line of response is. For Mary1 to know, in rich
detail, the experience that Mary2 is having, via Mary2’s
nervous system, would require an inference from the physical information to the
quale of sky blue itself. However, as
I have already pointed out, knowledge via inference is not of the same modal
kind as knowledge of qualia via direct
acquaintance. This modal difference should be sufficient to establish that even
if Mary1 we able to infer Mary2’s experience, should
would not gain information of the same modal kind, and consequently, Mary2
still has access to information not available to Mary1. So the above
conclusion that physicalism is false, must hold.
CONCLUSION
Frank Jackson’s thought
experiment with Mary, a brilliant young scientist, has been faced severe
criticism on many fronts. One critic, Daniel Dennett, has given perhaps the
most radical critique claiming that Jackson has given us a mere intuition pump.
Dennett further argues that given all physical
information it is possible that Mary learns nothing at all. I have demonstrate
that Dennett’s argument is a red herring in so far as he conflates notions of
“know how” with “know that.” We are not interested in whether or not Mary can
distinguish colors, we want to know if she learns something new. Additionally,
Dennett’s claim that Mary can gain information of qualia via an inference
from the physical facts is implausible on modal grounds. Consequently, in
running the Mary experiment again and providing a control I was able to
demonstrate that Jackson’s thought experiment avoids Dennett’s criticisms and
that Jackson’s initial conclusion can hold. Consequently, barring stronger
arguments from Dennett, it appears that physicalism is false and some form of
ontological dualism or pluralism is implied.
Works Cited:
Dennett, Daniel. Consciousness Explained (New York: Back
Books Company/Little, Brown and Company, 1991)
Jackson,
Frank. “Epiphenomenal Qualia.” The
Philosophical Quarterly (Apr. 1982) pp. 127-136
No comments:
Post a Comment